-M-

Macroparadigm MORPHOLOGY: a notion which is introduced in Carstairs (1987) to refer to a collection of °paradigms which are distinct in phonologically, morphosyntactically or semantically predictable ways. EXAMPLE: compare the following three Hungarian verbal paradigms:
stem	olvas	 'read' ül	'sit'   mond	 'say'
1 sg.	olvas-ok	ül-ök	 	mond-ok
2 sg.	olvas-ol	ül-sz	 	mond-asz
3 sg.	olvas		ül		mond
1 pl.	olvas-unk	ül-ünk 		mond-unk
2 pl.	olvas-tok	ül-tök 		mond-otok
3 pl.	olvas-nak	ül-nek	 	mond-anak
('s' = [s], 'sz' = [s])
Carstairs assumes that these three verbs belong to the same macroparadigm, since the variation is fully predictable. First, stems with back vowels (olvas, mond) select back vowel suffixes (-ok, -unk), while verb stems with front vowels select front vowels. This variation is due to a rule of vowel harmony. Second, if a consonant cluster of three members arises this is split up by an epenthetic vowel. Third, in the 2 sg. form a stem ending in a °sibilant takes the suffix -ol/-el, while other stems take -sz (or a variant).
LIT. Carstairs (1987), Spencer (1991).

Major category
SYNTAX: the categories N, V, and A and their projections.
LIT. Chomsky (1965, 1973).

Mapping Principle
SYNTAX: principle proposed in Marantz (1984) to relate independently constructed levels of representation to each other. In Marantz' model there are three levels of syntactic representation, logico-semantic structure (l-s-structure), syntactic structure (s-structure), and surface structure, together with a lexicon whose lexical entries contain information about argument structure, transitivity, semantic roles etc. The Mapping Principle guarantees that crucial aspects of structure, specifically those relating to grammatical relations, are automatically preserved from one level to the next.
MORPHOLOGY: principle proposed by Sproat (1985) to relate the phono-morphological and the syntactico-semantic level of representation of complex words to each other. He basically proposes the Mapping Principle to account for the so-called °bracketing paradoxes. EXAMPLE: A standard example of a bracketing paradox is ungrammaticality. The phono-morphological representation of this form will include the information that un- is an unstressed prefix, and that -ity is a suffix which attracts stress to the previous syllable. The syntactico-semantic representation will include the information that un- selects adjectives and means 'NOT', and that -ity creates abstract nouns from adjectives. Furthermore, at the phono-morphological level hierarchical structure plays a relatively small role. Instead, strict adjacency tends to be much more relevant. On the other hand, at the syntactico-semantic level, linear order seems to be of little importance. Here, hierarchical structure or sisterhood between morphemes is crucial. At the syntactico-semantic level the representations of ungrammaticality in (i) are equivalent, since linear order is irrelevant. At the phono-morphological level the representations of ungrammaticality in (ii) are also equivalent, since hierarchical structure is irrelevant at this level of representation:

(i)  [[UN [GRAMMATICAL]A ]A ITY]N <=> [ITY [UN [GRAMMATICAL]A ]A ]N 
   <=> [[GRAMMATICAL]A UN]A ITY]N <=> [ITY [[GRAMMATICAL]A UN]A ]N
 
(ii) [[un [grammatical]] ity] <=> [un [[grammatical] ity]]
Sproat defines his Mapping Principle in such a way that [[un [grammatical]] ity] can be rebracketed as [un [[grammatical] ity]], since morphological principles such as level ordering demand it.
LIT. Spencer (1991).

Mass noun
SEMANTICS: a noun which refers to something without clear boundaries or individual members, like milk and gold. Also called mass term. In English, mass nouns cannot be pluralized (cf. *milks) and cannot be used with the indefinite article (cf. *a milk) or with numerals (cf. *one milk). Mass nouns like cattle and furniture are sometimes called collective nouns because they refer to a collection of individuals, but not to any one individual. The opposite of a mass noun is called a °count noun.

Mass term
°Mass noun.

Material equivalence
°Equivalence.

Material implication
°Implication.

MAX(A)
SYNTAX: (minimalist theory) the least full-category maximal projection dominating A.
LIT. Chomsky (1992).

Maximal chain
°Chain.

Maximal onset principle
PHONOLOGY: a principle determining underlying °syllable division. It states that intervocalic °consonants are maximally assigned to the °onsets of syllables in conformity with universal and language-specific conditions (see also °sonority hierarchy). EXAMPLE: the English word diploma can be divided in several ways: dip.lo.ma vs. di.plo.ma. However, the only division that is in conformity with the maximal onset principle is di.plo.ma.
LIT. Kahn (1976), Selkirk (1981).

M-command
°C-command.

Meaning
°Extension and °Intension, °Denotation and °Connotation, °Meaning theories.

Meaning opposition
°Antonymy.

Meaning postulate
SEMANTICS: a device used in °logical semantics to stipulate semantic relations between lexical items. Meaning postulates were introduced in Carnap (1947) in order to account for the fact that a sentence like (i) is an °analytic truth, true in every °model. The meaning postulate in (ii) captures this analyticity:

(i)  Bachelors are unmarried
(ii) For all x, if x is a bachelor, then x is unmarried
Meaning postulates can be seen as an alternative for °decomposition of word meaning. They are extensively used in °Montague Grammar.
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Meaning theories
SEMANTICS: different views about the nature of meaning and the proper formulation of a semantic theory. There are roughly three theories about meaning: (i) the denotational theory, (ii) the conceptualist theory, (iii) the pragmatic theory.
(i) The denotational theory characterizes the meaning of an expression in terms of the notions °reference and °truth. The meaning of a sentence can be described by specifying when it is true, the meaning of other expressions can be described by specifying the entity or entities it refers to. Thus, the correspondence between language and the world is taken to be the crucial element of meaning (hence the name correspondence theory of meaning). The denotational theory is typical of °logical semantics which is °truth-conditional and °model-theoretic (Montague (1970), Gamut 1991).
(ii) The conceptualist theory identifies the meaning of an expression with the concepts or ideas associated with the expression, i.e. with a mental representation of the content of that expression, often making use of °decomposition of meaning. The semantic work which has been done within generative grammar is usually based on a conceptualist theory: °Katz-Fodor-semantics, °Generative Semantics, and °Conceptual Structure (Jackendoff 1983).
(iii) the pragmatic theory identifies the meaning of an expression with the use that is made of it by participants in an interaction. This theory is often named the meaning-is-use theory after Wittgenstein (1953). It is characteristic for those theories in which °speech acts play a central role, following Austin (1962). The three approaches need not be incompatible, because they all deal with different aspects of meaning (see Chierchia & McConnell-Ginet 1990).
LIT. Austin (1962), Chierchia & McConnell-Ginet (1990), Gamut (1991), Jackendoff (1983), Montague (1974), Wittgenstein (1953).

Meaning-is-use-theory
°Meaning theories.

Melody tier
PHONOLOGY: the part of a phonological representation which encodes the segmental contents of a specific phonological unit. EXAMPLE: in moraic theory long vowels are often considered to be identical to their short counterparts as far as their segmental contents is concerned. Therefore they are represented identically at the melody tier but have different moraic content. See °mora.

Mentalistic theory
°Meaning theories.

Meta language
SEMANTICS: the language that is used to talk about (expressions of) another language, the object language. Object language and meta language can be the same, e. g. ordinary English, but they always differ in function. If we cannot detect any meta language in a sentence, there is no object language either. The distinction was introduced to avoid the °liar's paradox.
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Meta-variable
SEMANTICS: an expression of a °meta language, that can be used to refer to arbitrary object language expressions in a logical language. EXAMPLE: the syntax definition of a °predicate logic could contain sentence (i).

(i) If phi is a formula in L, then so is Neg phi
In (i), phi is a metavariable standing for any formula of the logical language L.
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Metrical phonology
PHONOLOGY: a cover term which refers to several non-linear theories of stress. The non-linear theory of the representation of stress as introduced by Liberman (1975) and Liberman & Prince (1977) is a direct reaction to the linear analysis of stress proposed within the Sound Pattern-framework developed by Chomsky & Halle (1968), in which stress is considered a property of individual segments (i.e. °vowels). In metrical phonology stress is seen as a relational property obtaining between constituents, expressed in °metrical trees as a °binary relation between sister nodes which are labeled weak or strong. The theory of metrical phonology is further developed by e.g. Hayes (1980), Prince (1983), Kager (1989) and others.

Metrical tree
PHONOLOGY: a branching representation of stress, introduced by Liberman & Prince (1977), see also °metrical phonology. A metrical tree is a hierarchy in which °syllables are combined into °feet and feet into a word constituent. Higher level structure includes the °phonological phrase, °intonational phrase and °utterance (cf. Selkirk (1981), Nespor & Vogel (1986)). Pairs of sister nodes are labeled Weak-Strong or Strong-Weak (or by the °Lexical Category Prominence Rule). The English phrase achromatic lens is represented as follows:

                  / \
                 /   \
                /     \
               /       \
              w         s
	   /     \      |	where S = syllable, w = weak
         Fw       Fs    F	      F = foot,	    s = strong
        /  \     /  \    \ 
      Ss   Sw   Ss   Sw   S
      |     |   |    |    |
      a   chro  ma  tic lens
Hayes (1981) constrained metrical theory considerably by the introduction of a universally defined set of °parameters that characterize the stress systems of languages (i.e. °bounded/unbounded; °dominance (left/right), °direction of footing, °quantity-(in)sensitivity).

Minimal domain
SYNTAX: (minimalist theory) the smallest subset K of S, S a set of categories, such that for any element A of S, some element B of K reflexively dominates A.
LIT. Chomsky (1992).

Minimal free form
MORPHOLOGY: a term which refers to the smallest unit that can exist on its own in a sentence. Words are typically assumed to be minimal free forms.

Minimal Governing Category (MGC)
SYNTAX: Implementation of the notion °binding domain, proposed in Chomsky (1981). The MGC of alpha is defined as the minimal XP (maximal projection) that contains alpha, a °SUBJECT °accessible to alpha, and the °governor of alpha. EXAMPLE: in (i) the MGC of the °anaphor each other is the embedded IP, since it contains each other, the accessible subject the men, and the governor like. Hence, each other must be °bound within this IP in compliance with °condition A of the °binding theory, and may not be coindexed with the girls, which is not contained in its MGC.

(i) the girlsi believe that [IP the menj like each otherj/*i ]
LIT. Chomsky (1981).

Minimal sign
MORPHOLOGY: a term which is introduced into linguistic theory in De Saussure's Cours de linguistique générale. A minimal sign is the minimal meaningful unit of a language where the relation between (phonetic) form and meaning is purely arbitrary.
LIT. De Saussure (19313), Aronoff (1976).

Minimalist program
SYNTAX: a program aiming to eliminate from linguistic theory anything which is not 'virtually necessary'. In Chomsky (1992) it is claimed that e.g. d-structure and s-structure can be dispensed with.
LIT. Chomsky (1992).

Minimality Condition
SYNTAX: condition which ensures that there can be no ambiguity of government. The 'absolute' form of the Minimality Condition states that a projection of an intermediate head serves as a °barrier for government by another proper governor; it is defined as follows in Chomsky (1986b):

(i) gamma is a barrier for beta if gamma is a projection or the immediate 
    projection of delta, a zero-level category distinct from beta
The choice between 'a projection' and 'the immediate projection' depends on whether a specifier should be governed from outside or not. Thus, in (ii)
(ii)		X''
               /|
	   spec	X'
                |
		X

only X' is a barrier when 'the immediate projection' is chosen in (i), leaving the specifier position open to government from outside, while both X' and X'' are barriers for government when 'a projection' is chosen in (i). The Minimality Condition is intended to exclude ambiguity of government, meaning that barriers created by (i) are barriers for government only, not for movement. In other words, Minimality does not play a role in °Bounding theory, while it plays a crucial role in determining whether or not the °ECP is violated. Consider for instance (iii).
(iii) how did John announce [NP a plan [CP t2 to [ t1 fix the car t]]]
Here t2 cannot be °antecedent-governed by how, resulting in an ECP violation, because the projection of the N0-head plan serves as a Minimality barrier. In Rizzi (1990) the concept of Minimality is relativized, so that government is only blocked by an intermediate governor of the same kind (rather than by any intermediate head, as in (i)). This means that government by a constituent in an A' specifier position will be blocked if there is an intermediate A' specifier, government by a constituent in an A specifier position will be blocked if there is an intermediate A specifier, while head-government will be blocked by an intervening head.
LIT. Chomsky (1986b), Rizzi (1990).

Modal
SYNTAX: a modal expression indicates the attitude of the speaker with respect to the truth-value of the proposition expressed. EXAMPLE: maybe, probably, possibly, may, can, etc. Modal verbs (or 'auxiliaries' because of their defective flexion) are known to allow a non-modal interpretation. Thus you may go can either mean that the speaker feels that it is possible that you will go (the so-called epistemic reading) or it can mean that you are allowed to go (the so-called root interpretation).

Modal logic
SEMANTICS: the logic of sentences with modal expressions like necessarily and possibly. These expressions can be added as operators (say N and P) to standard logic:

(i)  If phi is a formula, then Nphi is a formula
(ii) If phi is a formula, then Pphi is a formula
Sentences like these are interpreted in terms of possible worlds. Nphi is true if phi is true in every possible world; Pphi is true if phi is true in some possible world.
LIT. Gamut (1991), Hughes & Cresswell (1968).

Modal verb
Verb which expresses modality. EXAMPLE: may, can, must, seem, etc.

Model
SEMANTICS: the device which makes it possible to interpret formal systems in model-theoretic semantics. The expressions of a formal language are then interpreted with respect to a model. In propositional logic, this model is an assignment of °truth values to the basic °propositional letters of the language. EXAMPLE: the following example shows how complex expressions are interpreted in terms of the truth values that the model assigns to the propositional letters p and q.

(i)  VM(p & q) = 1 if and only if VM(p) = 1 and VM(q) = 1
In predicate logic, the model M consists of a universe of discourse (D) and a mapping I from the °individual constants and °predicate letters to the °universe of discourse. As the example shows, the interpretation of the formula P(c) is determined by the denotations that P and c get from the model.
(ii) VM( P(c) ) = 1 iff IM(c) in IM(P)
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Model-theoretic semantics
°Model.

Modifier
Grammatical element which is neither an °argument nor a °predicate, but which modifies another element or phrase (e.g. a predicate). EXAMPLE: the adverb very is a modifier of the adjective ill in he is very ill.

Modularity
Basic notion in the °GB framework referring to the thesis that the human knowledge of language is modular, i.e. consists of distinct subsystems (modules). Examples of modules are the °Case system, the °X-bar system, and the °Binding system.
LIT. Chomsky (1981, 1986a).

Monotone decreasing
°Downward monotonicity.

Monotone increasing
°Upward monotonicity.

Monotonicity
SEMANTICS: determiners (and quantifiers) can be classified according to their monotonicity-properties. A determiner D in a sentence of the form [S [NP D CN] VP] establishes a relation between the interpretations of CN and VP taken as sets of individuals. The monotonicity-properties of D can be found by extending or restricting the interpretations of CN and VP, and checking whether the resulting sentence is still true. Left upward/downward monotonicity deals with the extension/restriction of CN; right upward/downward monotonicity deals with the extension/restriction of VP. Left upward monotonicity is often called Persistence and left downward monotonicity Antipersistence; right monotonicity is then simply called monotonicity.
LIT. Barwise & Cooper (1981), Gamut (1991).

Montague Grammar
SEMANTICS: cover term for the kind of syntactic and semantic work that is directly inspired by the work of the American philosopher Richard Montague. It is based on the idea that the meaning theories for natural languages and formal languages can and should be based on the same principles, according to a Universal Grammar, of which the °Compositionality Principle is the most important one. The clearest and most influential concrete illustration of Montague's ideas can be found in his article 'The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English' (usually referred to as PTQ) in which he defined the syntax and semantics of a considerable fragment of English. The system of rules and notations given there are the point of departure for Montague Grammar. In PTQ, Montague does not interpret expressions of English directly, but he translates English words and phrases into expressions of a logical language IL which are interpreted in the usual model-theoretic way. PTQ employs some of the most advanced logical instruments: the sentences of English are generated by a categorial grammar, the syntactic counterpart of °type logic, the logical language IL is a combination of °intensional logic and type logic with °lambda-abstraction which is interpreted relative to a model containing °possible worlds and moments of time, and crucial use is made of °meaning postulates. The range of constructions and phenomena treated in PTQ includes quantifier scope, opaque contexts, conjunction, infinitival complements and relative clauses.
LIT. Gamut (1991), Montague (1974).

Mood
SYNTAX: cover term for one of the four inflectional categories of verbs (mood, tense, aspect, and modality). The most common categories are associated with the way sentences are used: indicative (statement), imperative (command), optative (wish), etc. Sometimes the distinction between declaratives (I go) and interrogatives (Do I go?) is considered one of mood.

Mora
PHONOLOGY: a unit of °syllable weight in moraic theory. Moras are the units to which metrical structure may refer. EXAMPLE: long vowels are often considered to be bimoraic, while short ones are monomoraic. This would explain the difference in behaviour with respect to stress-rules between these two classes of vowels in °quantity-sensitive languages.
LIT. Hyman (1985), Prince (1983), Van der Hulst (1984), McCarthy & Prince (1986), Hayes (1989).

Morph
MORPHOLOGY: a term which refers to alternative forms or realizations of a single °morpheme. EXAMPLE: the English plural suffix is found in precisely three different pronounciations, /s/, /z/, and /@z/: cats /kats/, dogs /dogz/, and horses /ho:s@z/. Since these three elements all represent a single morpheme, they are called morphs, and we say that /s/, /z/, and /@z/ are °allomorphs of the abstract or underspecified plural suffix /-Z/.

Morpheme
MORPHOLOGY: a term which refers to the smallest component of a word that (a) seems to contribute some sort of meaning, or a grammatical function to the word to which it belongs, and (b) cannot itself be decomposed into smaller morphemes. EXAMPLE: the English word disagreement can be decomposed into three morphemes, viz. the prefix dis-, the base morpheme agree, and the suffix -ment.

Morpheme-based morphology
MORPHOLOGY: a theory in which it is assumed that word formation rules may operate over morphemes (e.g. Halle (1973), Siegel (1974), Kiparsky (1982)). This theory is an alternative to the theory of °word-based morphology (e.g. Aronoff (1976), Booij (1977), Scalise (1984)). In the latter theory it is assumed that new words are formed by applying a word formation rule to a single already existing word. Both the new word and the existing one are members of major lexical categories. EXAMPLE: English has the following verb classes:

(i)	X=fer	 X=mit	  X=sume   X=ceive    X=duce
	refer	 remit	  resume   receive   reduce
	defer	 demit		   deceive   deduce
	confer	 commit	  consume  conceive  conduce
	transfer transmit		     transduce
Apparently, we can isolate the prefixes re-, de-, con-, and trans- in these forms. However, the base forms fer, mit, sume, ceive, and duce do not exist as independent words. In a word-based morphology the words in (i) cannot be formed by a regular word formation rule. In a morpheme-based morphology, on the other hand, it is allowed to generate these verbs by prefixation rules. The question whether morphology is word based or morpheme based is still alive, and yet undecided.

Morpheme Structure Condition (MSC)
PHONOLOGY/MORPHOLOGY: conditions which express regularities about the phonological structure of morphemes. It is generally assumed that MSCs may be stated in two ways: either as positive MSCs or as negative ones. A positive MSC of English is that a morpheme may begin with up to three consonants where the first one must be /s/ (e.g. string). Negative ones are that English words may not begin with a velar nasal (*ngam), or end in /h/ (*pah). In recent theories of underspecification, conditions on the phonological shape of morphemes are sometimes expressed by lexical °redundancy rules.
LIT. Halle (1959), Stanley (1967), Chomsky & Halle (1968), Kiparsky (1982), Archangeli & Pulleyblank (1986).

Morphemic Tier Hypothesis (MTH)
PHONOLOGY/MORPHOLOGY: a hypothesis first introduced into the theory of °Autosegmental phonology in McCarthy (1981) which entails the claim that every morpheme making up a word is assigned a separate tier, i.e., a separate and autonomous level of representation. This hypothesis is mainly proposed to circumvent the °No-Crossing Constraint which says that association lines may not cross. EXAMPLE: the Arabic word katab is made out of the triliteral root ktb 'write', the perfective active morpheme a, and the °template CVCVC. If the morphemes ktb and a were represented at a single tier, association of these morphemes to the template CVCVC would result in a violation of the No-Crossing Constraint, as is shown in (i). By representing them at autonomous tiers as in (ii), this problem is solved:

 (i) *	C V C V	C	* C V C V C
        | | |   |         |   |   |
	k a t	b	  k   t   b  a

(ii)	    a
           / \
	C V C V	C
        |   |   |
	k   t	b
LIT. McCarthy (1981, 1986), Steriade (1986), Goldsmith (1990), Spencer (1991).

Morpholexical rule
MORPHOLOGY: a kind of lexical °redundancy rule proposed by Lieber (1980, 1982) to relate °allomorphs which are listed in the lexicon, to each other. Morpholexical rules apply in a subcomponent of the grammar which precedes both the word formation component proper and the phonological component. The main motivation for this type of rule is that there are cases in which word formation rules need to have access to derived allomorphs before the phonology applies. EXAMPLE: in the Australian language Warlbiri verbs have five conjugational classes, each taking a different set of allomorphs of tense suffixes. The present suffix has the allomorphs -nya, -nganya, -rninya, and -nanya. These forms are phonologically very similar, and it is tempting to derive them from a common underlying form by a kind of phonological rule. Warlbiri also has a rule of reduplication which basically says: copy the first two syllables or only the first if it has a long vowel. Given the fact that the suffix is either monosyllabic or bisyllabic, the precise shape of the allomorph must be known at the time the morphological rule of reduplication applies.

Morphological component
A component in the grammar in which the word formation rules apply. The question whether there is actually an autonomous morphological component is yet unresolved, and gave rise to Anderson's famous (1982) article "Where is Morphology?". Basically three main approaches can be distinguished. The first approach (e.g. Halle (1973), Halle & Vergnaud (1987) proposes a morphological component which is autonomous from syntax as well as phonology. In the second approach, morphology and phonology are intertwined, i.e., it is assumed that the rules of morphology and phonology apply within a single component: the Lexicon (e.g. Siegel (1974), Pesetsky (1979), Kiparsky (1982)). In the third approach, morphology is an integrated part of the syntactic component, which means that both are subject to the same set of principles and/or rules (e.g. Chomsky (1957), Lees (1960), Baker (1985), Lieber (1992)). Schultink (1988) and Spencer (1991) provide a survey of the most important theoretical positions held by generative linguists.

Morphological object
MORPHOLOGY: a term that is introduced in DiSciulllo & Williams (1987) to refer to one important conception of the notion 'word', viz. the conception of word as an entity constructed out of morphological atoms (= morphemes) by (concatenative) processes of affixation and compounding.
LIT. Di Sciullo & Williams (1987).

Morphological Transformation Prohibition (MTP)
MORPHOLOGY: a constraint proposed by McCarthy (1982a) which entails that transformations are excluded from the morphological component.

Move alpha
SYNTAX: most general formulation of possible °movements. In effect, Move alpha says that some category alpha can be moved anytime anywhere. It generalizes rules such as Move NP and Move wh, which in their turn generalize construction specific transformations such as °Passivization and °Raising. Move alpha itself is considered an instance of °Affect alpha.
LIT. Chomsky (1977b, 1980, 1981, 1986b), Lasnik & Saito (1984, 1991).

Movement
SYNTAX: the process which plays a role in deriving °S-structure from °D-structure and °LF from S-structure by the reordering of constituents. We say that an element at S-structure has been moved if there is a certain relationship between the element and an empty position elsewhere in the structure. EXAMPLE: in the question Who did he see, we interpret who as the direct object of see. This is explained if who is generated in the direct object position at D-structure (to the right of see) and has been moved to the first position in S-structure. This is a case of overt movement because the effect of movement is visible at °PF. When movement is involved in the derivation of LF, we speak of hidden or covert movement: the effect is invisible at the level of PF. Thus in a °multiple question like Who saw what, the second wh-phrase what is covertly moved to sentence initial position in the derivation of LF (see °wh-in-situ).
LIT. Chomsky (1965, 1973, 1986b, 1992).

M-selection
°S-selection.

Multiple question
SYNTAX: Question with more than one wh-phrase. EXAMPLE: Who bought what? In English, a multiple question has all but one of its wh-phrases in situ, since only one wh-phrase may be fronted (°wh-in-situ).
LIT. Chomsky (1981, 1986b).

Mutation
MORPHOLOGY/PHONOLOGY: a process by which a new word is formed without affixation, but simply by a change of the initial consonant of the base. EXAMPLE: in the Siberian language Nivkh (or Gilyak) nouns can be derived from verbs simply by changing the initial consonant (see (i)), and likewise transitive and intransitive verbs are often related solely by mutation (see (ii)):

(i)  vut^y id^y	'sweep'			put^yis	  'broom'
     fady	'put on knee-piece'	phad^y	  'knee-piece'

(ii) gesqod^y	'burn NP'		kesqod^y  'burn oneself'
     zod^y	'bend'			t^yod^y   'bend'

     (C^y = palatalized C, Ch = aspirated C)
LIT. Spencer (1991).

Mutative
°Inchoative.