-R-

Raising to object
SYNTAX: °NP-movement from an embedded subject position to a °c-commanding object position. This operation has been proposed in order to explain the fact that him in (i), although the subject of to have won, has the case-marking of a direct object.
(i) John believes himi [ti to have won]
The problem with this analysis is that an empty object position will have to be generated in order to provide a landing site for NP-movement. This is at odds with the °Projection Principle and in conflict with °Theta-theory. As a solution to this problem it has been proposed (e.g. in Chomsky 1991) that Raising-to-object is in fact movement to the specifier position in a °functional AGRP. °Exceptional Case Marking. Soames & Perlmutter suggest that 'Raising to object' is merely a metaphor, and that in fact, the embedded clause in (iii) contains a pro-drop (°pro) subject.
LIT. Soames & Perlmutter (1979), Postal (1974) Chomsky (1981, 1991), Koster (1987).

Raising to subject
°Subject Raising.

Reading
SYNTAX: if an expression has two (or more) readings, it has two (or more) logically distinct interpretations. If two expressions have a reading in common they share an interpretation.

Readjustment rule
MORPHOLOGY/PHONOLOGY: type of rule proposed by Chomsky & Halle (1968) to modify the output of the word formation rules or the output of the syntactic rules before these structures enter the phonological component. First, they change syntactic structure into phonological structure. Second, they change structures such as [[sing] PAST] into sung and other type of quasi phonological operations to adjust the output of the syntactic component.
LIT. Chomsky & Halle (1968), Aronoff (1976), Spencer (1991).

Reanalysis
SYNTAX: notion invoked in the analysis of °preposition stranding and °clause union phenomena. In the case of a °pseudo-passive like (i)a the stranded preposition at and the verb laughed are sometimes reanalyzed as the complex verb laughed at as in (i)b.

(i) a Johni was laughed [PP at ti]
    b Johni was [V laughed at] ti
Reanalysis eliminates the PP-boundary so that the NP-trace ti in (i)b can be °properly governed by laughed. Another kind of reanalysis has been proposed in order to handle operations on thematic relations. In these cases reanalysis may collapse (or merge) two °external theta-roles in °restructuring constructions containing a modal verb, see (ii), but it may also demote an external theta-role to become an internal one in °causative constructions, see (iii), while creating a complex predicate. Both examples are Italian:
(ii)  Giorgio vuole sapere per che.
      Giorgio wants know   why
(iii) Giorgio fa dormire i bambini
      Giorgio makes sleep the children
In (ii) Giorgio would fulfill the external theta-roles of vuole and sapere which are merged to one. In (iii) i bambini fulfills the external theta-role of dormire, but this role would be turned into an internal role of the complex fa dormire. Since these kinds of operations are at odds with the °theta criterion and the °Projection Principle, two-dimensional phrase-structures have been proposed, assigning more than one representation simultaneously to one sentence, in order to circumvent these problems. One structure is determined basically by theta-relations corresponding to a non-reanalyzed D-structure, the other represents the reanalyzed °clause union structure. °Co-analysis.
LIT. Lasnik & Kupin (1976), Haegeman & van Riemsdijk (1987), Zubizarreta (1982, 1987), Manzini (1983a), Koster (1987), Di Sciullo & Williams (1987).
MORPHOLOGY: a process by which the structure of a string of elements is changed without an overt linear change. EXAMPLE: Pesetsky's (1985) °Quantifier Raising changes the morphological structure of unhappier (= [un [happy+er]]) into the semantically motivated structure [[un+happy] er]. Another example of reanalysis is Baker's (1988) Abstract Incorporation.

Reciprocal
SYNTAX: element such as each other in (i).

(i) [John and Mary]i can't stand each otheri
Reciprocals behave as °anaphors with respect to °binding theory, and require a plural antecedent (*that gang hates each other).
LIT. Chomsky (1981), Heim, Lasnik & May (1991).

Reconstruction
SYNTAX: operation proposed in Chomsky (1977b) in the derivation of °LF from °S-structure, which returns material °pied-piped by °Wh-movement to the extraction site so as to derive an °operator-variable chain headed by the Wh-operator itself. EXAMPLE: by reconstruction, the LF (i)b is derived from the SS (i)a:

(i) a  which book about Mary does he like t
    b  which x, does he like [ x book about Mary ]
As a result, interpretation of the LF is relatively straightforward. Syntactic evidence for reconstruction comes from the behavior of pied-piped material with respect to binding theory. EXAMPLE: in (ii),
(ii)   which book about himself does John like t
the °anaphor himself can apparently be °bound by the NP John, which does not, however, °c-command it at SS. This can be explained if the constituent containing the anaphor is returned to its pre-movement position prior to the operation of binding condition A. Other analyses of such "reconstruction phenomena" can involve an extended notion of c-command, a reordering of the model of grammar (van Riemsdijk & Williams 1981), or a view of movement as copying and deletion (Chomsky 1992).
LIT. Chomsky (1977b, 1992), Van Riemsdijk & Williams (1981) Williams (1994).

Recoverability (of deletion)
SYNTAX: condition saying that an element may be deleted only if it is fully determined by a structurally related phrase, or if it is a 'designated element'. Part of the recoverability condition is subsumed under the °ECP. See °deletion.
LIT. Chomsky (1981).

Recursion
MORPHOLOGY/SYNTAX: process or result of elements recurring in a structure. Recursion allows structure to become of unbounded length. EXAMPLE: compounding in English is recursive as is shown by the examples in (i): the concatenation of nouns can go on forever.

(i)   film society 
    > student film society 
    > student film society committee 
    > student film society committee scandal 
    > student film society committee scandal inquiry > etc.
LIT. Chomsky (1957), Spencer (1991).

Redundancy rule
MORPHOLOGY/PHONOLOGY: rule which fills in predictable or redundant information. Redundancy rules have two important properties: (a) they do not create structure, and (b) they do not alter structure. EXAMPLE: the fact that sonorants in English are always voiced, as opposed to obstruents, can be captured by leaving the feature [voice] unspecified, and fill in [+voice] by a redundancy rule. The idea behind redundancy rules and °underspecification is that redundant information can be left unspecified in the grammar (usually the lexicon), and that a grammar which contains less (idiosyncratic) information is more highly valued than a grammar which contains more (every thing else being the same).
LIT. Halle (1959), Stanley (1967), Chomsky & Halle (1968), Kiparsky (1982), Archangeli (1984).

Reduplication
MORPHOLOGY/PHONOLOGY: a word formation process by which some part of a base (= a segment, syllable, morpheme) is repeated, either to the left, or to the right, or, occasionally, in the middle. EXAMPLE: Tagalog, a language spoken at the Philippines has many reduplication rules, resulting in forms like (i) and (ii):

(i)  sulat			'writing'
     su-sulat   		'will write'
(ii) mag-sulat-sulat	        'to write intermittently'
LIT. Marantz (1982), Broselow & McCarthy (1983), Clements (1985), Spencer (1991).

Reference
SEMANTICS: Frege introduced the distinction between sense (German: Sinn) and reference (German: Bedeutung). The reference of an expression is the entity or set of entities which that expression denotes. The sense of an expression relates to properties of the (mental) representation of the expression. For example, the reference of the president of the USA is George Bush in December 1992, but Bill Clinton in February 1993. The sense of the phrase, however, is the same in both cases. Reference and sense are often equated with °extension and °intension.
LIT. Gamut (1991).
SYNTAX: °referential NPs are assumed to be referential due to their reference. This reference is usually conceived of as a function which associates the NP with some entity or entities in a mental domain of interpretation. The reference of an NP is indicated by a referential index (e.g. Johni).
LIT. Chomsky (1981, 1986a).

Reference time
SEMANTICS: the third time point R in Reichenbach's theory of tense which is used next to the points S (°speech time) and E (°event time) to represent the meaning of tenses. The relevance of R can be seen most clearly in the different representation of simple past and present perfect:

simple past		I saw John
			
			...---R,E -----S--->...
			
present perfect		I have seen John
			
			...---E-----S,R--->...
Given that the reference point can be interpreted as the time from which an event is 'seen', the difference is that in the simple past the event is seen from some moment in the past, while in the present perfect the event is seen from the present.
LIT. Reichenbach (1947), Gamut (1991).

Referential index
SYNTAX: formal device used to indicate °reference. EXAMPLE: in Johni saw himselfi and Maryi saw Johnj the subscripts i and j are the referential indices (or indexes). °Coindexing.
LIT. Chomsky (1980, 1981), Lasnik (1989), Fiengo & May (1994).

Referential noun phrase
SEMANTICS: a noun phrase that refers to an individual (or group of individuals) as opposed to noun phrases that quantify (°quantificational noun phrase) or noun phrases that are used as predicates (°predicational noun phrase). EXAMPLE: Typical examples of referential noun phrases are proper names and definite noun phrases like this book, my car and John's children.

Referential use
SEMANTICS: the use that a speaker makes of a definite noun phrase when he uses the content of the noun phrase to identify an individual. The definite noun phrase in The murderer of Smith is insane is used referentially when the speaker intends to refer to a particular person which he knows to be the murderer of Smith. Donnellan (1966) distinguishes the referential use of definite noun phrases from their °attributive use.
LIT. Donnellan (1966).

Referential opacity
MORPHOLOGY: a property of words which entails that it is impossible to 'see inside' them, and refer to their parts by using an anaphoric device such as a pronoun. EXAMPLE: there cannot be an anaphoric relation between it and tea in the compound teapot. Therefore, if the sentence he took the teapot and poured it into the cup means that he poured the tea into the cup, the fact that it refers to the tea does not arise through the anaphoric relation that is possible in he took the tea and poured it into the cup. Referential opacity is closely related to the property of °lexical integrity.

Referentiality
SYNTAX: traditionally, an expression is a referential expression if it has a reference, hence designates an individual in some domain of interpretation. Recently the notion of a referential expression is equated with that of an argument, arguments being the terms which are associated with thematic roles such as Agent, Theme, etc. The set of arguments includes at least proper names (John), anaphors (himself), and pronouns (he). The notion of referentiality is involved in the analysis of idioms (the bucket in the idiom he kicked the bucket is not referential), weather-predicates ( it in it rains is quasi-referential) and expletives such as it (cf. it seems that he has gone) and there (there is a man in the garden). Referential expressions are not to be confused with so-called R-expressions, i.e. NPs which are subject to condition C of the °binding-theory ('R-expressions must be free').

Reflexive
SYNTAX: expression such as himself in English, which must be anaphorically related to an antecedent. EXAMPLE: herself in (i) is a reflexive with Mary as its antecedent.

(i) Maryi dresses herselfi well
Reflexives behave as °anaphors with respect to the °binding theory.
LIT. Chomsky (1981).

Relatedness paradox
°Bracketing paradox.

Relative clause
SYNTAX: a clause which is introduced by a °relative pronoun and which modifies its NP antecedent:

(i) The Ferrari [which I can't afford e]
EXAMPLE: In this example the Ferrari is the antecedent of the relative clause which I can't afford e, and which is the relative pronoun. The relative clause always contains a gap - e - which is the °trace of the relative pronoun. Movement of the relative pronoun is usually treated on a par with °wh-movement. °Relativization, °Restrictive Relative Clause.
LIT. Smits (1989).

Relative pronoun
SYNTAX: pronoun such as who, which, where etc. introducing a °relative clause.

Relativization
SYNTAX: process by which a relative clause (e.g. the man [who you see e]) is derived from an underlying non-relative clause (the man [you see the man]). The derivation includes NP-deletion under identity (the man), insertion of a relative pronoun (who), and wh-movement. This analysis has been replaced by one in which relative pronouns are base-generated.
LIT. Chomsky (1965), Smits (1989).

Relativized head
MORPHOLOGY: a notion proposed in DiSciullo & Williams (1987) which replaces Williams' (1981a) notion of °head. They define the notion 'relativized head' as in (i).

(i) The headF (= head with respect to the feature F) of a word is the 
    rightmost element of the word marked for the feature F
The difference between the notions 'head' and 'relativized head' is far from trivial. The notion 'head' is an absolute notion, in the sense that one constituent of a complex word is marked as the head, and features marked on this constituent undergo °Feature Percolation. The notion 'relativized head' entails that a constituent can be the head with respect to one particular feature, but a non-head with respect to another. EXAMPLE: if the rightmost constituent has the feature [+F] and [uG] (where [uG] means 'not marked for feature G'), and its lefthand sister constituent has the feature [+G], the righthand constituent is the relativized head with respect to the feature [F], whereas the lefthand constituent is the relativized head with respect to the feature [G]. As a consequence the Feature Percolation Conventions percolate up the feature [+F] from the righthand constituent and [+G] from the lefthand one.
LIT. Lieber (1980), Selkirk (1982), Di Sciullo & Williams (1987).

Relativized Righthand Head Rule
°Relativized head and °Righthand Head Rule.

Remnant Extraposition
°Third Construction.

Remnant Topicalization
SYNTAX: topicalization of the remnant of a VP. EXAMPLE: in (i) the object diese Bücher has been taken out of the VP, and the remnant gelesen has been topicalized.

(i) [VP gelesen] hat er diese Bücher nicht.
Supposedly, the object is extracted from the VP by °scrambling.
LIT. Webelhuth & den Besten (1987).

Residue
SYNTAX: (minimalist theory) the residue of A is the °domain of A minus the °complement domain.
LIT. Chomsky (1992).

Restricted quantifier
SEMANTICS: a quantifier which ranges over a subset of the °universe of discourse selected by means of a predicate. Restricted quantification is sometimes represented as in (i), with the restricted quantifier between brackets and the predicate P indicating the subset:

(i)  [ All(x) : P(x) ] Q(x)
     [ ThereIs(x) : P(x) ] Q(x)
It can also be represented in standard predicate logic by means of connectives:
(ii) All(x) [ P(x) -> Q(x) ]
     ThereIs(x) [ P(x) & Q(x) ] 
In (ii) quantification is restricted to P: all or some entities that are P have property Q. In natural language, quantifiers are always restricted; either by the common noun following the quantifying determiner (every man, some woman) or by an inherent meaning element (everyone, something).
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Restrictive relative clause
Relative clause which is used to restrict the class of entities that can be denoted by a noun phrase. EXAMPLE: in the books that John read, the restrictive relative clause that John read restricts the set of books to those that are read by John. Non-restrictive relative clauses add further qualifications to the reference of the noun phrase but do not narrow down (nor expand) its extension. Thus in this book, which John gave to me, the non-restrictive relative clause does not restrict the set of books. The difference between a restrictive and a non-restrictive interpretation is often only expressed intonationally.

Restructuring
SYNTAX: process which unites two clauses yielding one clause. EXAMPLE: The following examples are from Italian. (ii) is the result of Restructuring:

(i)   [Si vuole [PRO vendere queste case a caro prezzo]]
      one wants      sell    these houses at a high price
(ii)  Queste casei si vogliono vendere ei a caro prezzo
In (i) it would be impossible to move the object queste case from the embedded clause into the matrix subject position, but, after Restructuring, this is exactly what happens in (ii). In general, Restructuring is assumed in order to explain °clause union phenomena in Romance languages, such as °Clitic Climbing and long movement as illustrated in (ii). No satisfactory formalization of Restructuring as a rule is available. A °verb raising type of analysis, which would create a verb cluster, must be rejected, because non-verbal material, such as adverbs and complementizers, can intervene between the two verbs:
(iii) Loi verró subito a vedere ei
      (I) it-will come at-once to see
      I will come at once to see it
The Barriers framework, with some extensions, allows an analysis in which °L-marking basically cancels the barrierhood of the complement clause, which otherwise would block clitic climbing. Clitic climbing then reduces to repeated application of °head movement. An intervening complementizer - a in (iii) - remains a potential problem.
LIT. Rizzi (1982: chapter 1), Manzini (1983a), Zubizarreta (1982), Burzio (1986), Kayne (1989).
MORPHOLOGY: °Reanalysis.

Result nominal
A result nominal is a nominal which denotes the result of the action denoted by the verb it is derived from. EXAMPLE: in (i)a the collection refers to an entity which is the result of collecting things.

(i) a  the collection was sold
    b  the collection of these particles has only begun
Result nominals are distinguished from process nominals which designate an event rather than an entity. In (i)b, the collection of these particles is a process nominal.
LIT. Grimshaw (1990).

Resultative (construction)
SYNTAX: verbs which denote an activity may be combined with a predicate to render a so-called resultative interpretation:

(i)   He smashed [the vase to pieces]
(ii)  They talked [him out of it]
(iii) She washed [the dirt off her face]
(iv)  The gardener watered [the flowers flat]
The brackets in (i)-(iv) reflect the °small clause analysis of resultative constructions. This analysis has not remained unchallenged.
LIT. Hoekstra (1988), Carrier & Randall (1992).

Resumptive pronoun (strategy)
SYNTAX: pronoun which appears in the position of the °variable bound by a wh-phrase. EXAMPLE: in (i) him is a resumptive pronoun bound by who and interpreted as a °bound variable.

(i) I wonder [whoi they think [that [if Mary marries himi] then 
    everybody will be happy]]
The appearance of resumptive pronouns is marginal in standard English, but quite acceptable in French and colloquial English. Theoretically, the construction is exceptional as well. Since the if-clause creates an °Adjunct Island, extraction of who out of the object position of marries is ungrammatical, as shown in (ii):
(ii) * I wonder [whoi they think [that [if Mary marries ei] then 
       everybody will be happy]]
The resulting °chain presumably violates °subjacency. In (i), on the other hand, who has not been moved. But being an operator, it must bind a variable, in this case the resumptive pronoun him.
LIT. Chomsky (1981, 1982), Zribi-Hertz (1984).

Retroflex
PHONOLOGY: retroflex sounds are produced by curling back the tongue tip past the °alveolar ridge. EXAMPLE: Northern-American [r] in bird.

Re-write rules
°Phrase structure rules.

R-expression
SYNTAX: element whose reference cannot usually be determined (but see °anaphoric epithet) anaphorically in the sense of the °binding theory and as such is distinguished from °anaphors and °pronominals. R-expressions are also distinguished from °quantificational and °predicational NPs in that they must be in an °A-position in °LF. With respect to °A-binding, variables - either wh-traces or traces of °QR - count as R-expressions. R-expressions are not to be confused with °referential expressions. With respect to °binding theory, R-expressions obey condition C, which says that they must be °A-free. This explains the illformedness of (ii) and (iii) (°Strong Crossover).

(ii)  *	hei thinks that Johni is a fool
(iii) *	whoi does hei like ti

Right downward monotonicity
SEMANTICS: a particular semantic property of some NPs, interpreted as °generalized quantifiers Q. Q has the property of being right downward monotone if and only if in a domain of entities E condition (i) holds.

(i) for all X,Y subset E: if X in Q, and Y subset X, then Y in Q
Right downward monotonicity can be tested as in (ii): not every N is right downward monotone, every N is not.
(ii) Not every dog walks =>  not every dog walks rapidly
     Every dog walks    =/=> every dog walks rapidly
So, a true sentence of the form [S NP VP] with a right downward monotone NP entails the truth of [S NP VP'], where the interpretation of VP' is a subset of the interpretation of VP. Right downward monotonicity can also be defined for determiners.
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Right monotonicity
°Right downward monotonicity, °Right upward monotonicity.

Right Node Raising
SYNTAX: operation of reduction on coordinated clauses whose rightmost constituents are identical. EXAMPLE: Right Node Raising derives the structure in (i)b from the underlying structure in (i)a by adjoining one copy of the identical constituents (the book) to the right of the sentence, and deleting the identical originals (indicated by e).

(i) a  [[John saw the book] and [Bill bought the book]]
    b  [[John saw ei] and [Bill bought ei]] the booki
LIT. Postal (1974).

Right Roof Constraint
SYNTAX: condition on °rightward movement first formulated by Ross (1967:185):

(i)  In all rules whose structural index is of the form ... A Y, and 
     whose structural change specifies that A is to be adjoined to the 
     right of Y, A must command Y.
This condition captures the fact that rightward movement is upward bounded, as the following contrast (adapted from Ross 1967:166) shows. The PP cannot leave its clause:
(ii)   [That [a review ti] came out yesterday [of this article]i] 
       is catastrophic

(iii) *[That [a review ti] came out yesterday] is catastrophic 
       [of this article]i
The notion of 'command' in (i) is not as strict as °c-command: it goes up to the first S. The name - Right Roof Constraint - is due to Soames & Perlmutter (1979).
LIT. Ross (1967), Soames & Perlmutter (1979).

Right upward monotonicity
SEMANTICS: an NP, interpreted as a °quantifier Q, has the property of being right upward monotone if and only if for all subsets X and Y of the domain of entities E condition (i) holds.

(i)  if X in Q and X subset Y, then Y in Q
Right upward monotonicity can be tested as in (ii): all N is right upward monotone, at most two N is not.
(ii) All dogs walked rapidly          =>  all dogs walked
(iv) At most two dogs walked rapidly =/=> at most two dogs walked
So a true sentence of the form [S NP VP] with a right upward monotone NP entails the truth of [S NP VP'], where the interpretation of VP' is a °superset of the interpretation of VP. Right upward monotonicity can also be defined for determiners.
LIT. Gamut (1991).

Righthand Head Rule (RHR)
MORPHOLOGY: a principle proposed in Williams (1981a) which says that the righthand member of a morphologically complex word is the °head of that word. This entails that the rightmost constituent determines all the properties of the whole. The RHR explains, among other things, the fact that the righthand member of compounds as well as the suffix of derived words determine uniquely the lexical category. EXAMPLE: Compare the following examples:

(i)  offP + whiteA	->  off whiteA
     dryA + dockN	->  dry dockN
     barN + tendV	->  bar tendV
(ii) feverN + ishA	->  feverishA
     instructV +ionN	->  destructionN
     standardN + izeV	->  standardizeV
LIT. Williams (1981a), Selkirk (1982), Di Sciullo & Williams (1987).

Rightward movement
°Extraposition, °Heavy-NP shift.

Rigid designator
SEMANTICS: an expression that refers to the same entity in every possible world. According to Kripke (1972), this is the case with proper names, i.e. names of individuals. The definite description the president of the US may refer to different persons in different worlds, but the denotation of the proper name Richard Nixon is the same person in every possible world. Kripke accounts for the relation between a name and its bearer by a causal theory of reference: the first use of a name for an individual determines its designation independent of its meaning properties (initial baptism). Kripke (1972) made the claim that natural kind terms (i.e. names of biological sorts, natural or mineral substances) are also rigid designators.
LIT. Kripke (1972), Gamut (1991).

Root
MORPHOLOGY: a term which is not uniquely defined. Some linguists consider the root to be the basic free morpheme in a derived form. EXAMPLE: if we take the form disagreement, this word contains the basic free morpheme agree and the two bound morphemes (or affixes) dis- and -ment. Some linguists (e.g. Spencer (1991)) call agree the root. Others (e.g. Halle (1973)) assume that agree is the stem, and reserve the notion 'root' for bounded morphemes which cannot be considered as affixes. For example, if we take the words receive, conceive and deceive, we can isolate the prefixes re-, con- and de- and the bound morpheme ceive. Only Halle (1973) calls ceive the root.

Root clause
SYNTAX: main clause which is not embedded. In °Verb Second languages root clauses differ from embedded clauses in that the finite verb is in second position.
LIT. Emonds (1976), Den Besten (1989).

Root compound
MORPHOLOGY: compound whose head is not deverbal or whose non-head does not have the function of argument of the verb from which the head is derived. EXAMPLE: English compounds such as housewife, blackbird, overcoat, rattlesnake, well-formed, off-white, overlook, and so on do not have a deverbal head, and therefore can be called root compounds. A compound such as truck driver on the other hand has a deverbal head and the non-head is an argument of the embedded verb drive. The distinction between root compounds and synthetic compounds has played a major role in theoretical discussions since the late seventies. Another term for root compound is primary compound. °Synthetic compound.
LIT. Roeper & Siegel (1978), Selkirk (1982), Lieber (1983), Fabb (1984), Sproat (1985), Roeper (1987, 1988), Spencer (1991).

Root-and-pattern morphology
°Nonconcatenative morphology.

Root modal
°Modal.

Round
PHONOLOGY: a °feature which characterizes sounds that are produced by rounding the lips. EXAMPLE: In English, [o] is [+round] and [i] is [-round].

Rule feature
MORPHOLOGY: a type of diacritic feature which triggers (or blocks) the application of a phonological rule. This feature is usually assumed to account for irregular word formation. EXAMPLE: Alternations such as foot:feet, goose:geese and tooth:teeth can be accounted for by assuming that the words foot, goose and tooth, have a rule feature [+U] which triggers the phonological umlaut rule.
LIT. Chomsky & Halle (1968), Zonneveld (1978), Kenstowics & Kisseberth (1979).

Rule of referral
°Syncretism.
LIT. Chomsky (1981, 1986a).